Denotational: Denotational semantics of untyped lambda calculus π§
Prev • Source • Next
module plfa.part3.Denotational where
The lambda calculus is a language about functions, that is, mappings from input to output. In computing we often think of such mappings as being carried out by a sequence of operations that transform an input into an output. But functions can also be represented as data. For example, one can tabulate a function, that is, create a table where each row has two entries, an input and the corresponding output for the function. Function application is then the process of looking up the row for a given input and reading off the output.
We shall create a semantics for the untyped lambda calculus based on this idea of functions-as-tables. However, there are two difficulties that arise. First, functions often have an infinite domain, so it would seem that we would need infinitely long tables to represent functions. Second, in the lambda calculus, functions can be applied to functions. They can even be applied to themselves! So it would seem that the tables would contain cycles. One might start to worry that advanced techniques are necessary to to address these issues, but fortunately this is not the case!
The first problem, of functions with infinite domains, is solved by observing that in the execution of a terminating program, each lambda abstraction will only be applied to a finite number of distinct arguments. (We come back later to discuss diverging programs.) This observation is another way of looking at Dana Scottβs insight that only continuous functions are needed to model the lambda calculus.
The second problem, that of self-application, is solved by relaxing the way in which we lookup an argument in a functionβs table. Naively, one would look in the table for a row in which the input entry exactly matches the argument. In the case of self-application, this would require the table to contain a copy of itself. Impossible! (At least, it is impossible if we want to build tables using inductive data type definitions, which indeed we do.) Instead it is sufficient to find an input such that every row of the input appears as a row of the argument (that is, the input is a subset of the argument). In the case of self-application, the table only needs to contain a smaller copy of itself, which is fine.
With these two observations in hand, it is straightforward to write down a denotational semantics of the lambda calculus.
Imports
open import Agda.Primitive using (lzero; lsuc) open import Data.Empty using (β₯-elim) open import Data.Product using (_Γ_; Ξ£; Ξ£-syntax; β; β-syntax; projβ; projβ) renaming (_,_ to β¨_,_β©) open import Data.Sum open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_β‘_; _β’_; refl; sym; cong; congβ; cong-app) open import Relation.Nullary using (Β¬_) open import Relation.Nullary.Negation using (contradiction) open import Function using (_β_) open import plfa.part2.Untyped using (Context; β ; _β_; β ; _,_; Z; S_; _β’_; `_; _Β·_; Ζ_; #_; twoαΆ; ext; rename; exts; subst; subst-zero; _[_]) open import plfa.part2.Substitution using (Rename; extensionality; rename-id)
Values
The Value
data type represents a finite portion of a function. We think of a value as a finite set of pairs that represent input-output mappings. The Value
data type represents the set as a binary tree whose internal nodes are the union operator and whose leaves represent either a single mapping or the empty set.
The β₯ value provides no information about the computation.
A value of the form
v β¦ w
is a single input-output mapping, from inputv
to outputw
.A value of the form
v β w
is a function that maps inputs to outputs according to bothv
andw
. Think of it as taking the union of the two sets.
infixr 7 _β¦_ infixl 5 _β_ data Value : Set where β₯ : Value _β¦_ : Value β Value β Value _β_ : Value β Value β Value
The β
relation adapts the familiar notion of subset to the Value data type. This relation plays the key role in enabling self-application. There are two rules that are specific to functions, β-fun
and β-dist
, which we discuss below.
infix 4 _β_ data _β_ : Value β Value β Set where β-bot : β {v} β β₯ β v β-conj-L : β {u v w} β v β u β w β u ----------- β (v β w) β u β-conj-R1 : β {u v w} β u β v ----------- β u β (v β w) β-conj-R2 : β {u v w} β u β w ----------- β u β (v β w) β-trans : β {u v w} β u β v β v β w ----- β u β w β-fun : β {v w vβ² wβ²} β vβ² β v β w β wβ² ------------------- β (v β¦ w) β (vβ² β¦ wβ²) β-dist : β{v w wβ²} --------------------------------- β v β¦ (w β wβ²) β (v β¦ w) β (v β¦ wβ²)
The first five rules are straightforward. The rule β-fun
captures when it is OK to match a higher-order argument vβ² β¦ wβ²
to a table entry whose input is v β¦ w
. Considering a call to the higher-order argument. It is OK to pass a larger argument than expected, so v
can be larger than vβ²
. Also, it is OK to disregard some of the output, so w
can be smaller than wβ²
. The rule β-dist
says that if you have two entries for the same input, then you can combine them into a single entry and joins the two outputs.
The β
relation is reflexive.
β-refl : β {v} β v β v β-refl {β₯} = β-bot β-refl {v β¦ vβ²} = β-fun β-refl β-refl β-refl {vβ β vβ} = β-conj-L (β-conj-R1 β-refl) (β-conj-R2 β-refl)
The β
operation is monotonic with respect to β
, that is, given two larger values it produces a larger value.
βββ : β {v w vβ² wβ²} β v β vβ² β w β wβ² ----------------------- β (v β w) β (vβ² β wβ²) βββ dβ dβ = β-conj-L (β-conj-R1 dβ) (β-conj-R2 dβ)
The β-dist
rule can be used to combine two entries even when the input values are not identical. One can first combine the two inputs using β and then apply the β-dist
rule to obtain the following property.
ββ¦β-dist : β{v vβ² w wβ² : Value} β (v β vβ²) β¦ (w β wβ²) β (v β¦ w) β (vβ² β¦ wβ²) ββ¦β-dist = β-trans β-dist (βββ (β-fun (β-conj-R1 β-refl) β-refl) (β-fun (β-conj-R2 β-refl) β-refl))
If the join u β v
is less than another value w
, then both u
and v
are less than w
.
ββ-invL : β{u v w : Value} β u β v β w --------- β u β w ββ-invL (β-conj-L lt1 lt2) = lt1 ββ-invL (β-conj-R1 lt) = β-conj-R1 (ββ-invL lt) ββ-invL (β-conj-R2 lt) = β-conj-R2 (ββ-invL lt) ββ-invL (β-trans lt1 lt2) = β-trans (ββ-invL lt1) lt2 ββ-invR : β{u v w : Value} β u β v β w --------- β v β w ββ-invR (β-conj-L lt1 lt2) = lt2 ββ-invR (β-conj-R1 lt) = β-conj-R1 (ββ-invR lt) ββ-invR (β-conj-R2 lt) = β-conj-R2 (ββ-invR lt) ββ-invR (β-trans lt1 lt2) = β-trans (ββ-invR lt1) lt2
Environments
An environment gives meaning to the free variables in a term by mapping variables to values.
Env : Context β Set Env Ξ = β (x : Ξ β β ) β Value
We have the empty environment, and we can extend an environment.
`β : Env β `β () infixl 5 _`,_ _`,_ : β {Ξ} β Env Ξ β Value β Env (Ξ , β ) (Ξ³ `, v) Z = v (Ξ³ `, v) (S x) = Ξ³ x
We can recover the initial environment from an extended environment, and the last value. Putting them back together again takes us where we started.
init : β {Ξ} β Env (Ξ , β ) β Env Ξ init Ξ³ x = Ξ³ (S x) last : β {Ξ} β Env (Ξ , β ) β Value last Ξ³ = Ξ³ Z init-last : β {Ξ} β (Ξ³ : Env (Ξ , β )) β Ξ³ β‘ (init Ξ³ `, last Ξ³) init-last {Ξ} Ξ³ = extensionality lemma where lemma : β (x : Ξ , β β β ) β Ξ³ x β‘ (init Ξ³ `, last Ξ³) x lemma Z = refl lemma (S x) = refl
The nth function takes a de Bruijn index and finds the corresponding value in the environment.
nth : β{Ξ} β (Ξ β β ) β Env Ξ β Value nth x Ο = Ο x
We extend the β
relation point-wise to environments with the following definition.
_`β_ : β {Ξ} β Env Ξ β Env Ξ β Set _`β_ {Ξ} Ξ³ Ξ΄ = β (x : Ξ β β ) β Ξ³ x β Ξ΄ x
We define a bottom environment and a join operator on environments, which takes the point-wise join of their values.
`β₯ : β {Ξ} β Env Ξ `β₯ x = β₯ _`β_ : β {Ξ} β Env Ξ β Env Ξ β Env Ξ (Ξ³ `β Ξ΄) x = Ξ³ x β Ξ΄ x
The β-refl
, β-conj-R1
, and β-conj-R2
rules lift to environments. So the join of two environments Ξ³
and Ξ΄
is greater than the first environment Ξ³
or the second environment Ξ΄
.
`β-refl : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} β Ξ³ `β Ξ³ `β-refl {Ξ} {Ξ³} x = β-refl {Ξ³ x} β-env-conj-R1 : β {Ξ} β (Ξ³ : Env Ξ) β (Ξ΄ : Env Ξ) β Ξ³ `β (Ξ³ `β Ξ΄) β-env-conj-R1 Ξ³ Ξ΄ x = β-conj-R1 β-refl β-env-conj-R2 : β {Ξ} β (Ξ³ : Env Ξ) β (Ξ΄ : Env Ξ) β Ξ΄ `β (Ξ³ `β Ξ΄) β-env-conj-R2 Ξ³ Ξ΄ x = β-conj-R2 β-refl
Denotational Semantics
We define the semantics with a judgment of the form Ο β’ M β v
, where Ο
is the environment, M
the program, and v
is a result value. For readers familiar with big-step semantics, this notation will feel quite natural, but donβt let the similarity fool you. There are subtle but important differences! So here is the definition of the semantics, which we discuss in detail in the following paragraphs.
infix 3 _β’_β_ data _β’_β_ : β{Ξ} β Env Ξ β (Ξ β’ β ) β Value β Set where var : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {x} --------------- β Ξ³ β’ (` x) β Ξ³ x β¦-elim : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {L M v w} β Ξ³ β’ L β (v β¦ w) β Ξ³ β’ M β v --------------- β Ξ³ β’ (L Β· M) β w β¦-intro : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {N v w} β Ξ³ `, v β’ N β w ------------------- β Ξ³ β’ (Ζ N) β (v β¦ w) β₯-intro : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {M} --------- β Ξ³ β’ M β β₯ β-intro : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {M v w} β Ξ³ β’ M β v β Ξ³ β’ M β w --------------- β Ξ³ β’ M β (v β w) sub : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {M v w} β Ξ³ β’ M β v β w β v --------- β Ξ³ β’ M β w
Consider the rule for lambda abstractions, β¦-intro
. It says that a lambda abstraction results in a single-entry table that maps the input v
to the output w
, provided that evaluating the body in an environment with v
bound to its parameter produces the output w
. As a simple example of this rule, we can see that the identity function maps β₯
to β₯
.
id : β β’ β id = Ζ # 0
denot-id : β {Ξ³ v} β Ξ³ β’ id β v β¦ v denot-id = β¦-intro var denot-id-two : β {Ξ³ v w} β Ξ³ β’ id β (v β¦ v) β (w β¦ w) denot-id-two = β-intro denot-id denot-id
Of course, we will need tables with many rows to capture the meaning of lambda abstractions. These can be constructed using the β-intro
rule. If term M (typically a lambda abstraction) can produce both tables v
and w
, then it produces the combined table v β w
. One can take an operational view of the rules β¦-intro
and β-intro
by imagining that when an interpreter first comes to a lambda abstraction, it pre-evaluates the function on a bunch of randomly chosen arguments, using many instances of the rule β¦-intro
, and then joins them into a big table using many instances of the rule β-intro
. In the following we show that the identity function produces a table containing both of the previous results, β₯ β¦ β₯
and (β₯ β¦ β₯) β¦ (β₯ β¦ β₯)
.
denot-id3 : `β β’ id β (β₯ β¦ β₯) β (β₯ β¦ β₯) β¦ (β₯ β¦ β₯) denot-id3 = denot-id-two
We most often think of the judgment Ξ³ β’ M β v
as taking the environment Ξ³
and term M
as input, producing the result v
. However, it is worth emphasizing that the semantics is a relation. The above results for the identity function show that the same environment and term can be mapped to different results. However, the results for a given Ξ³
and M
are not too different, they are all finite approximations of the same function. Perhaps a better way of thinking about the judgment Ξ³ β’ M β v
is that the Ξ³
, M
, and v
are all inputs and the semantics either confirms or denies whether v
is an accurate partial description of the result of M
in environment Ξ³
.
Next we consider the meaning of function application as given by the β¦-elim
rule. In the premise of the rule we have that L
maps v
to w
. So if M
produces v
, then the application of L
to M
produces w
.
As an example of function application and the β¦-elim
rule, we apply the identity function to itself. Indeed, we have both that β
β’ id β (u β¦ u) β¦ (u β¦ u)
and also β
β’ id β (u β¦ u)
, so we can apply the rule β¦-elim
.
id-app-id : β {u : Value} β `β β’ id Β· id β (u β¦ u) id-app-id {u} = β¦-elim (β¦-intro var) (β¦-intro var)
Next we revisit the Church numeral two. This function has two parameters: a function and an arbitrary value u
, and it applies the function twice. So the function must map u
to some value, which weβll name v
. Then for the second application, it must map v
to some value. Letβs name it w
. So the parameterβs table must contain two entries, both u β¦ v
and v β¦ w
. For each application of the table, we extract the appropriate entry from it using the sub
rule. In particular, we use the β-conj-R1 and β-conj-R2 to select u β¦ v
and v β¦ w
, respectively, from the table u β¦ v β v β¦ w
. So the meaning of twoαΆ is that it takes this table and parameter u
, and it returns w
. Indeed we derive this as follows.
denot-twoαΆ : β{u v w : Value} β `β β’ twoαΆ β ((u β¦ v β v β¦ w) β¦ (u β¦ w)) denot-twoαΆ {u}{v}{w} = β¦-intro (β¦-intro (β¦-elim (sub var lt1) (β¦-elim (sub var lt2) var))) where lt1 : v β¦ w β u β¦ v β v β¦ w lt1 = β-conj-R2 (β-fun β-refl β-refl) lt2 : u β¦ v β u β¦ v β v β¦ w lt2 = (β-conj-R1 (β-fun β-refl β-refl))
Next we have a classic example of self application: Ξ = Ξ»x. (x x)
. The input value for x
needs to be a table, and it needs to have an entry that maps a smaller version of itself, call it v
, to some value w
. So the input value looks like v β¦ w β v
. Of course, then the output of Ξ
is w
. The derivation is given below. The first occurrences of x
evaluates to v β¦ w
, the second occurrence of x
evaluates to v
, and then the result of the application is w
.
Ξ : β β’ β Ξ = (Ζ (# 0) Β· (# 0)) denot-Ξ : β {v w} β `β β’ Ξ β ((v β¦ w β v) β¦ w) denot-Ξ = β¦-intro (β¦-elim (sub var (β-conj-R1 β-refl)) (sub var (β-conj-R2 β-refl)))
One might worry whether this semantics can deal with diverging programs. The β₯
value and the β₯-intro
rule provide a way to handle them. (The β₯-intro
rule is also what enables Ξ² reduction on non-terminating arguments.) The classic Ξ©
program is a particularly simple program that diverges. It applies Ξ
to itself. The semantics assigns to Ξ©
the meaning β₯
. There are several ways to derive this, we shall start with one that makes use of the β-intro
rule. First, denot-Ξ
tells us that Ξ
evaluates to ((β₯ β¦ β₯) β β₯) β¦ β₯
(choose vβ = vβ = β₯
). Next, Ξ
also evaluates to β₯ β¦ β₯
by use of β¦-intro
and β₯-intro
and to β₯
by β₯-intro
. As we saw previously, whenever we can show that a program evaluates to two values, we can apply β-intro
to join them together, so Ξ
evaluates to (β₯ β¦ β₯) β β₯
. This matches the input of the first occurrence of Ξ
, so we can conclude that the result of the application is β₯
.
Ξ© : β β’ β Ξ© = Ξ Β· Ξ denot-Ξ© : `β β’ Ξ© β β₯ denot-Ξ© = β¦-elim denot-Ξ (β-intro (β¦-intro β₯-intro) β₯-intro)
A shorter derivation of the same result is by just one use of the β₯-intro
rule.
denot-Ξ©' : `β β’ Ξ© β β₯ denot-Ξ©' = β₯-intro
Just because one can derive β
β’ M β β₯
for some closed term M
doesnβt mean that M
necessarily diverges. There may be other derivations that conclude with M
producing some more informative value. However, if the only thing that a term evaluates to is β₯
, then it indeed diverges.
An attentive reader may have noticed a disconnect earlier in the way we planned to solve the self-application problem and the actual β¦-elim
rule for application. We said at the beginning that we would relax the notion of table lookup, allowing an argument to match an input entry if the argument is equal or greater than the input entry. Instead, the β¦-elim
rule seems to require an exact match. However, because of the sub
rule, application really does allow larger arguments.
β¦-elim2 : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {Mβ Mβ vβ vβ vβ} β Ξ³ β’ Mβ β (vβ β¦ vβ) β Ξ³ β’ Mβ β vβ β vβ β vβ ------------------ β Ξ³ β’ (Mβ Β· Mβ) β vβ β¦-elim2 dβ dβ lt = β¦-elim dβ (sub dβ lt)
Exercise denot-plusαΆ
(practice)
What is a denotation for plusαΆ
? That is, find a value v
(other than β₯
) such that β
β’ plusαΆ β v
. Also, give the proof of β
β’ plusαΆ β v
for your choice of v
.
-- Your code goes here
Denotations and denotational equality
Next we define a notion of denotational equality based on the above semantics. Its statement makes use of an if-and-only-if, which we define as follows.
_iff_ : Set β Set β Set P iff Q = (P β Q) Γ (Q β P)
Another way to view the denotational semantics is as a function that maps a term to a relation from environments to values. That is, the denotation of a term is a relation from environments to values.
Denotation : Context β Setβ Denotation Ξ = (Env Ξ β Value β Set)
The following function β° gives this alternative view of the semantics, which really just amounts to changing the order of the parameters.
β° : β{Ξ} β (M : Ξ β’ β ) β Denotation Ξ β° M = Ξ» Ξ³ v β Ξ³ β’ M β v
In general, two denotations are equal when they produce the same values in the same environment.
infix 3 _β_ _β_ : β {Ξ} β (Denotation Ξ) β (Denotation Ξ) β Set (_β_ {Ξ} Dβ Dβ) = (Ξ³ : Env Ξ) β (v : Value) β Dβ Ξ³ v iff Dβ Ξ³ v
Denotational equality is an equivalence relation.
β-refl : β {Ξ : Context} β {M : Denotation Ξ} β M β M β-refl Ξ³ v = β¨ (Ξ» x β x) , (Ξ» x β x) β© β-sym : β {Ξ : Context} β {M N : Denotation Ξ} β M β N ----- β N β M β-sym eq Ξ³ v = β¨ (projβ (eq Ξ³ v)) , (projβ (eq Ξ³ v)) β© β-trans : β {Ξ : Context} β {Mβ Mβ Mβ : Denotation Ξ} β Mβ β Mβ β Mβ β Mβ ------- β Mβ β Mβ β-trans eq1 eq2 Ξ³ v = β¨ (Ξ» z β projβ (eq2 Ξ³ v) (projβ (eq1 Ξ³ v) z)) , (Ξ» z β projβ (eq1 Ξ³ v) (projβ (eq2 Ξ³ v) z)) β©
Two terms M
and N
are denotational equal when their denotations are equal, that is, β° M β β° N
.
The following submodule introduces equational reasoning for the β
relation.
module β-Reasoning {Ξ : Context} where infix 1 start_ infixr 2 _ββ¨β©_ _ββ¨_β©_ infix 3 _β start_ : β {x y : Denotation Ξ} β x β y ----- β x β y start xβy = xβy _ββ¨_β©_ : β (x : Denotation Ξ) {y z : Denotation Ξ} β x β y β y β z ----- β x β z (x ββ¨ xβy β© yβz) = β-trans xβy yβz _ββ¨β©_ : β (x : Denotation Ξ) {y : Denotation Ξ} β x β y ----- β x β y x ββ¨β© xβy = xβy _β : β (x : Denotation Ξ) ----- β x β x (x β) = β-refl
Road map for the following chapters
The subsequent chapters prove that the denotational semantics has several desirable properties. First, we prove that the semantics is compositional, i.e., that the denotation of a term is a function of the denotations of its subterms. To do this we shall prove equations of the following shape.
β° (` x) β ...
β° (Ζ M) β ... β° M ...
β° (M Β· N) β ... β° M ... β° N ...
The compositionality property is not trivial because the semantics we have defined includes three rules that are not syntax directed: β₯-intro
, β-intro
, and sub
. The above equations suggest that the dentoational semantics can be defined as a recursive function, and indeed, we give such a definition and prove that it is equivalent to β°.
Next we investigate whether the denotational semantics and the reduction semantics are equivalent. Recall that the job of a language semantics is to describe the observable behavior of a given program M
. For the lambda calculus there are several choices that one can make, but they usually boil down to a single bit of information:
- divergence: the program
M
executes forever. - termination: the program
M
halts.
We can characterize divergence and termination in terms of reduction.
- divergence:
Β¬ (M ββ Ζ N)
for any termN
. - termination:
M ββ Ζ N
for some termN
.
We can also characterize divergence and termination using denotations.
- divergence:
Β¬ (β β’ M β v β¦ w)
for anyv
andw
. - termination:
β β’ M β v β¦ w
for somev
andw
.
Alternatively, we can use the denotation function β°
.
- divergence:
Β¬ (β° M β β° (Ζ N))
for any termN
. - termination:
β° M β β° (Ζ N)
for some termN
.
So the question is whether the reduction semantics and denotational semantics are equivalent.
(β N. M ββ Ζ N) iff (β N. β° M β β° (Ζ N))
We address each direction of the equivalence in the second and third chapters. In the second chapter we prove that reduction to a lambda abstraction implies denotational equality to a lambda abstraction. This property is called the soundness in the literature.
M ββ Ζ N implies β° M β β° (Ζ N)
In the third chapter we prove that denotational equality to a lambda abstraction implies reduction to a lambda abstraction. This property is called adequacy in the literature.
β° M β β° (Ζ N) implies M ββ Ζ Nβ² for some Nβ²
The fourth chapter applies the results of the three preceeding chapters (compositionality, soundness, and adequacy) to prove that denotational equality implies a property called contextual equivalence. This property is important because it justifies the use of denotational equality in proving the correctness of program transformations such as performance optimizations.
The proofs of all of these properties rely on some basic results about the denotational semantics, which we establish in the rest of this chapter. We start with some lemmas about renaming, which are quite similar to the renaming lemmas that we have seen in previous chapters. We conclude with a proof of an important inversion lemma for the less-than relation regarding function values.
Renaming preserves denotations
We shall prove that renaming variables, and changing the environment accordingly, preserves the meaning of a term. We generalize the renaming lemma to allow the values in the new environment to be the same or larger than the original values. This generalization is useful in proving that reduction implies denotational equality.
As before, we need an extension lemma to handle the case where we proceed underneath a lambda abstraction. Here, the nth function performs lookup in the environment, analogous to Ξ β A
. Now suppose that Ο
is a renaming that maps variables in Ξ³
into variables with equal or larger values in Ξ΄
. This lemmas says that extending the renaming producing a renaming ext r
that maps Ξ³ , v
to Ξ΄ , v
.
ext-nth : β {Ξ Ξ v} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {Ξ΄ : Env Ξ} β (Ο : Rename Ξ Ξ) β Ξ³ `β (Ξ΄ β Ο) ------------------------------ β (Ξ³ `, v) `β ((Ξ΄ `, v) β ext Ο) ext-nth Ο lt Z = β-refl ext-nth Ο lt (S nβ²) = lt nβ²
We proceed by cases on the de Bruijn index n
.
If it is
Z
, then we just need to show thatv β‘ v
, which we have byrefl
.If it is
S nβ²
, then the goal simplifies tonth nβ² Ξ³ β‘ nth (Ο nβ²) Ξ΄
, which is an instance of the premise.
Now for the renaming lemma. Suppose we have a renaming that maps variables in Ξ³
into variables with the same values in Ξ΄
. If M
results in v
when evaluated in environment Ξ³
, then applying the renaming to M
produces a program that results in the same value v
when evaluated in Ξ΄
.
rename-pres : β {Ξ Ξ v} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {Ξ΄ : Env Ξ} {M : Ξ β’ β } β (Ο : Rename Ξ Ξ) β Ξ³ `β (Ξ΄ β Ο) β Ξ³ β’ M β v --------------------- β Ξ΄ β’ (rename Ο M) β v rename-pres Ο lt (var {x = x}) = sub var (lt x) rename-pres Ο lt (β¦-elim d dβ) = β¦-elim (rename-pres Ο lt d) (rename-pres Ο lt dβ) rename-pres Ο lt (β¦-intro d) = β¦-intro (rename-pres (ext Ο) (ext-nth Ο lt) d) rename-pres Ο lt β₯-intro = β₯-intro rename-pres Ο lt (β-intro d dβ) = β-intro (rename-pres Ο lt d) (rename-pres Ο lt dβ) rename-pres Ο lt (sub d ltβ²) = sub (rename-pres Ο lt d) ltβ²
The proof is by induction on the semantics of M
. As you can see, all of the cases are trivial except the cases for variables and lambda.
For a variable
x
, we make use of the premise to show thatnth x Ξ³ β‘ nth (Ο x) Ξ΄
.For a lambda abstraction, the induction hypothesis requires us to extend the renaming. We do so, and use the
ext-nth
lemma to show that the extended renaming maps variables to ones with equivalent values.
Identity renamings and environment strengthening
We shall need a corollary of the renaming lemma that says that if M
results in v
, then we can replace a value in the environment with a larger one (a stronger one), and M
still results in v
. In particular, if Ξ³ β’ M β v
and Ξ³ β Ξ΄
, then Ξ΄ β’ M β v
. What does this have to do with renaming? Itβs renaming with the identity function. So we apply the renaming lemma with the identity renaming, which gives us Ξ΄ β’ rename (Ξ» {A} x β x) M β v
, and then we apply the rename-id
lemma to obtain Ξ΄ β’ M β v
.
β-env : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {Ξ΄ : Env Ξ} {M v} β Ξ³ β’ M β v β Ξ³ `β Ξ΄ ---------- β Ξ΄ β’ M β v β-env{Ξ}{Ξ³}{Ξ΄}{M}{v} d lt with rename-pres{Ξ}{Ξ}{v}{Ξ³}{Ξ΄}{M} (Ξ» {A} x β x) lt d ... | dβ² rewrite rename-id {Ξ}{β }{M} = dβ²
In the proof that substitution reflects denotations, in the case for lambda abstraction, we use a minor variation of β-env
, in which just the last element of the environment gets larger.
up-env : β {Ξ} {Ξ³ : Env Ξ} {M v uβ uβ} β (Ξ³ `, uβ) β’ M β v β uβ β uβ ----------------- β (Ξ³ `, uβ) β’ M β v up-env d lt = β-env d (nth-le lt) where nth-le : β {Ξ³ uβ uβ} β uβ β uβ β (Ξ³ `, uβ) `β (Ξ³ `, uβ) nth-le lt Z = lt nth-le lt (S n) = β-refl
Inversion of the less-than relation for functions
What can we deduce from knowing that a function v β¦ w
is less than some value u
? What can we deduce about u
? The answer to this question is called the inversion property of less-than for functions. This question is not easy to answer because of the β-dist
rule, which relates a function on the left to a pair of functions on the right. So u
may include several functions that, as a group, relate to v β¦ w
. Furthermore, because of the rules β-conj-R1
and β-conj-R2
, there may be other values inside u
, such as β₯
, that have nothing to do with v β¦ w
. But in general, we can deduce that u
includes a collection of functions where the join of their domains is less than v
and the join of their codomains is greater than w
.
To precisely state and prove this inversion property, we need to define what it means for a value to include a collection of values. We also need to define how to compute the join of their domains and codomains.
Value membership and inclusion
Recall that we think of a value as a set of entries with the join operator v β w
acting like set union. The function value v β¦ w
and bottom value β₯
constitute the two kinds of elements of the set. (In other contexts one can instead think of β₯
as the empty set, but here we must think of it as an element.) We write u β v
to say that u
is an element of v
, as defined below.
infix 5 _β_ _β_ : Value β Value β Set u β β₯ = u β‘ β₯ u β v β¦ w = u β‘ v β¦ w u β (v β w) = u β v β u β w
So we can represent a collection of values simply as a value. We write v β w
to say that all the elements of v
are also in w
.
infix 5 _β_ _β_ : Value β Value β Set v β w = β{u} β u β v β u β w
The notions of membership and inclusion for values are closely related to the less-than relation. They are narrower relations in that they imply the less-than relation but not the other way around.
βββ : β{u v : Value} β u β v ----- β u β v βββ {.β₯} {β₯} refl = β-bot βββ {v β¦ w} {v β¦ w} refl = β-refl βββ {u} {v β w} (injβ x) = β-conj-R1 (βββ x) βββ {u} {v β w} (injβ y) = β-conj-R2 (βββ y) βββ : β{u v : Value} β u β v ----- β u β v βββ {β₯} s with s {β₯} refl ... | x = β-bot βββ {u β¦ uβ²} s with s {u β¦ uβ²} refl ... | x = βββ x βββ {u β uβ²} s = β-conj-L (βββ (Ξ» z β s (injβ z))) (βββ (Ξ» z β s (injβ z)))
We shall also need some inversion principles for value inclusion. If the union of u
and v
is included in w
, then of course both u
and v
are each included in w
.
ββ-inv : β{u v w : Value} β (u β v) β w --------------- β u β w Γ v β w ββ-inv uvw = β¨ (Ξ» x β uvw (injβ x)) , (Ξ» x β uvw (injβ x)) β©
In our value representation, the function value v β¦ w
is both an element and also a singleton set. So if v β¦ w
is a subset of u
, then v β¦ w
must be a member of u
.
β¦βββ : β{v w u : Value} β v β¦ w β u --------- β v β¦ w β u β¦βββ incl = incl refl
Function values
To identify collections of functions, we define the following two predicates. We write Fun u
if u
is a function value, that is, if u β‘ v β¦ w
for some values v
and w
. We write all-funs v
if all the elements of v
are functions.
data Fun : Value β Set where fun : β{u v w} β u β‘ (v β¦ w) β Fun u all-funs : Value β Set all-funs v = β{u} β u β v β Fun u
The value β₯
is not a function.
Β¬Funβ₯ : Β¬ (Fun β₯) Β¬Funβ₯ (fun ())
In our values-as-sets representation, our sets always include at least one element. Thus, if all the elements are functions, there is at least one that is a function.
all-funsβ : β{u} β all-funs u β Ξ£[ v β Value ] Ξ£[ w β Value ] v β¦ w β u all-funsβ {β₯} f with f {β₯} refl ... | fun () all-funsβ {v β¦ w} f = β¨ v , β¨ w , refl β© β© all-funsβ {u β uβ²} f with all-funsβ Ξ» z β f (injβ z) ... | β¨ v , β¨ w , m β© β© = β¨ v , β¨ w , (injβ m) β© β©
Domains and codomains
Returning to our goal, the inversion principle for less-than a function, we want to show that v β¦ w β u
implies that u
includes a set of function values such that the join of their domains is less than v
and the join of their codomains is greater than w
.
To this end we define the following dom and cod functions. Given some value u
(that represents a set of entries), dom u
returns the join of their domains and cod u
returns the join of their codomains.
dom : (u : Value) β Value dom β₯ = β₯ dom (v β¦ w) = v dom (u β uβ²) = dom u β dom uβ² cod : (u : Value) β Value cod β₯ = β₯ cod (v β¦ w) = w cod (u β uβ²) = cod u β cod uβ²
We need just one property each for dom
and cod
. Given a collection of functions represented by value u
, and an entry v β¦ w β u
, we know that v
is included in the domain of v
.
β¦βββdom : β{u v w : Value} β all-funs u β (v β¦ w) β u ---------------------- β v β dom u β¦βββdom {β₯} fg () uβv β¦βββdom {v β¦ w} fg refl uβv = uβv β¦βββdom {u β uβ²} fg (injβ vβ¦wβu) uβv = let ih = β¦βββdom (Ξ» z β fg (injβ z)) vβ¦wβu in injβ (ih uβv) β¦βββdom {u β uβ²} fg (injβ vβ¦wβuβ²) uβv = let ih = β¦βββdom (Ξ» z β fg (injβ z)) vβ¦wβuβ² in injβ (ih uβv)
Regarding cod
, suppose we have a collection of functions represented by u
, but all of them are just copies of v β¦ w
. Then the cod u
is included in w
.
ββ¦βcodβ : β{u v w : Value} β u β v β¦ w --------- β cod u β w ββ¦βcodβ {β₯} s refl with s {β₯} refl ... | () ββ¦βcodβ {C β¦ Cβ²} s m with s {C β¦ Cβ²} refl ... | refl = m ββ¦βcodβ {u β uβ²} s (injβ x) = ββ¦βcodβ (Ξ» {C} z β s (injβ z)) x ββ¦βcodβ {u β uβ²} s (injβ y) = ββ¦βcodβ (Ξ» {C} z β s (injβ z)) y
With the dom
and cod
functions in hand, we can make precise the conclusion of the inversion principle for functions, which we package into the following predicate named factor
. We say that v β¦ w
factors u
into uβ²
if uβ²
is a included in u
, if uβ²
contains only functions, its domain is less than v
, and its codomain is greater than w
.
factor : (u : Value) β (uβ² : Value) β (v : Value) β (w : Value) β Set factor u uβ² v w = all-funs uβ² Γ uβ² β u Γ dom uβ² β v Γ w β cod uβ²
We prove the inversion principle for functions by induction on the derivation of the less-than relation. To make the induction hypothesis stronger, we broaden the premise to uβ β uβ
(instead of v β¦ w β u
), and strengthen the conclusion to say that for every function value v β¦ w β uβ
, we have that v β¦ w
factors uβ
into some value uβ
.
Inversion of less-than for functions, the case for β-trans
The crux of the proof is the case for β-trans
.
uβ β u u β uβ
--------------- (β-trans)
uβ β uβ
By the induction hypothesis for uβ β u
, we know that v β¦ w factors u into uβ²
, for some value uβ²
, so we have all-funs uβ²
and uβ² β u
. By the induction hypothesis for u β uβ
, we know that for any vβ² β¦ wβ² β u
, vβ² β¦ wβ²
factors uβ
into uβ
. With these facts in hand, we proceed by induction on uβ²
to prove that (dom uβ²) β¦ (cod uβ²)
factors uβ
into uβ
. We discuss each case of the proof in the text below.
sub-inv-trans : β{uβ² uβ u : Value} β all-funs uβ² β uβ² β u β (β{vβ² wβ²} β vβ² β¦ wβ² β u β Ξ£[ uβ β Value ] factor uβ uβ vβ² wβ²) --------------------------------------------------------------- β Ξ£[ uβ β Value ] factor uβ uβ (dom uβ²) (cod uβ²) sub-inv-trans {β₯} {uβ} {u} fuβ² uβ²βu IH = β₯-elim (contradiction (fuβ² refl) Β¬Funβ₯) sub-inv-trans {uββ² β¦ uββ²} {uβ} {u} fg uβ²βu IH = IH (β¦βββ uβ²βu) sub-inv-trans {uββ² β uββ²} {uβ} {u} fg uβ²βu IH with ββ-inv uβ²βu ... | β¨ uββ²βu , uββ²βu β© with sub-inv-trans {uββ²} {uβ} {u} (Ξ» {vβ²} z β fg (injβ z)) uββ²βu IH | sub-inv-trans {uββ²} {uβ} {u} (Ξ» {vβ²} z β fg (injβ z)) uββ²βu IH ... | β¨ uββ , β¨ fu21' , β¨ uβββuβ , β¨ duβββduββ² , cuββ²βcuββ β© β© β© β© | β¨ uββ , β¨ fu22' , β¨ uβββuβ , β¨ duβββduββ² , cuββ²βcuββ β© β© β© β© = β¨ (uββ β uββ) , β¨ fuββ² , β¨ uββ²βuβ , β¨ βββ duβββduββ² duβββduββ² , βββ cuββ²βcuββ cuββ²βcuββ β© β© β© β© where fuββ² : {vβ² : Value} β vβ² β uββ β vβ² β uββ β Fun vβ² fuββ² {vβ²} (injβ x) = fu21' x fuββ² {vβ²} (injβ y) = fu22' y uββ²βuβ : {C : Value} β C β uββ β C β uββ β C β uβ uββ²βuβ {C} (injβ x) = uβββuβ x uββ²βuβ {C} (injβ y) = uβββuβ y
Suppose
uβ² β‘ β₯
. Then we have a contradiction because it is not the case thatFun β₯
.Suppose
uβ² β‘ uββ² β¦ uββ²
. Thenuββ² β¦ uββ² β u
and we can apply the premise (the induction hypothesis fromu β uβ
) to obtain thatuββ² β¦ uββ²
factors ofuβ into uββ²
. This case is complete becausedom uβ² β‘ uββ²
andcod uβ² β‘ uββ²
.Suppose
uβ² β‘ uββ² β uββ²
. Then we haveuββ² β u
anduββ² β u
. We also haveall-funs uββ²
andall-funs uββ²
, so we can apply the induction hypothesis for bothuββ²
anduββ²
. So there exists valuesuββ
anduββ
such that(dom uββ²) β¦ (cod uββ²)
factorsu
intouββ
and(dom uββ²) β¦ (cod uββ²)
factorsu
intouββ
. We will show that(dom u) β¦ (cod u)
factorsu
intouββ β uββ
. So we need to show thatdom (uββ β uββ) β dom (uββ² β uββ²) cod (uββ² β uββ²) β cod (uββ β uββ)
But those both follow directly from the factoring of
u
intouββ
anduββ
, using the monotonicity ofβ
with respect toβ
.
Inversion of less-than for functions
We come to the proof of the main lemma concerning the inversion of less-than for functions. We show that if uβ β uβ
, then for any v β¦ w β uβ
, we can factor uβ
into uβ
according to v β¦ w
. We proceed by induction on the derivation of uβ β uβ
, and describe each case in the text after the Agda proof.
sub-inv : β{uβ uβ : Value} β uβ β uβ β β{v w} β v β¦ w β uβ ------------------------------------- β Ξ£[ uβ β Value ] factor uβ uβ v w sub-inv {β₯} {uβ} β-bot {v} {w} () sub-inv {uββ β uββ} {uβ} (β-conj-L lt1 lt2) {v} {w} (injβ x) = sub-inv lt1 x sub-inv {uββ β uββ} {uβ} (β-conj-L lt1 lt2) {v} {w} (injβ y) = sub-inv lt2 y sub-inv {uβ} {uββ β uββ} (β-conj-R1 lt) {v} {w} m with sub-inv lt m ... | β¨ uββ , β¨ fuββ , β¨ uβββuββ , β¨ domuβββv , wβcoduββ β© β© β© β© = β¨ uββ , β¨ fuββ , β¨ (Ξ» {w} z β injβ (uβββuββ z)) , β¨ domuβββv , wβcoduββ β© β© β© β© sub-inv {uβ} {uββ β uββ} (β-conj-R2 lt) {v} {w} m with sub-inv lt m ... | β¨ uββ , β¨ fuββ , β¨ uβββuββ , β¨ domuβββv , wβcoduββ β© β© β© β© = β¨ uββ , β¨ fuββ , β¨ (Ξ» {C} z β injβ (uβββuββ z)) , β¨ domuβββv , wβcoduββ β© β© β© β© sub-inv {uβ} {uβ} (β-trans{v = u} uββu uβuβ) {v} {w} vβ¦wβuβ with sub-inv uββu vβ¦wβuβ ... | β¨ uβ² , β¨ fuβ² , β¨ uβ²βu , β¨ domuβ²βv , wβcoduβ² β© β© β© β© with sub-inv-trans {uβ²} fuβ² uβ²βu (sub-inv uβuβ) ... | β¨ uβ , β¨ fuβ , β¨ uββuβ , β¨ domuββdomuβ² , coduβ²βcoduβ β© β© β© β© = β¨ uβ , β¨ fuβ , β¨ uββuβ , β¨ β-trans domuββdomuβ² domuβ²βv , β-trans wβcoduβ² coduβ²βcoduβ β© β© β© β© sub-inv {uββ β¦ uββ} {uββ β¦ uββ} (β-fun lt1 lt2) refl = β¨ uββ β¦ uββ , β¨ (Ξ» {w} β fun) , β¨ (Ξ» {C} z β z) , β¨ lt1 , lt2 β© β© β© β© sub-inv {uββ β¦ (uββ β uββ)} {uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ} β-dist {.uββ} {.(uββ β uββ)} refl = β¨ uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ , β¨ f , β¨ g , β¨ β-conj-L β-refl β-refl , β-refl β© β© β© β© where f : all-funs (uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ) f (injβ x) = fun x f (injβ y) = fun y g : (uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ) β (uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ) g (injβ x) = injβ x g (injβ y) = injβ y
Let v
and w
be arbitrary values.
Case
β-bot
. Souβ β‘ β₯
. We havev β¦ w β β₯
, but that is impossible.Case
β-conj-L
.uββ β uβ uββ β uβ ------------------- uββ β uββ β uβ
Given that
v β¦ w β uββ β uββ
, there are two subcases to consider.Subcase
v β¦ w β uββ
. We conclude by the induction hypothesis foruββ β uβ
.Subcase
v β¦ w β uββ
. We conclude by the induction hypothesis foruββ β uβ
.
Case
β-conj-R1
.uβ β uββ -------------- uβ β uββ β uββ
Given that
v β¦ w β uβ
, the induction hypothesis foruβ β uββ
gives us thatv β¦ w
factorsuββ
intouββ
for someuββ
. To show thatv β¦ w
also factorsuββ β uββ
intouββ
, we just need to show thatuββ β uββ β uββ
, but that follows directly fromuββ β uββ
.Case
β-conj-R2
. This case follows by reasoning similar to the case forβ-conj-R1
.Case
β-trans
.uβ β u u β uβ --------------- uβ β uβ
By the induction hypothesis for
uβ β u
, we know thatv β¦ w
factorsu
intouβ²
, for some valueuβ²
, so we haveall-funs uβ²
anduβ² β u
. By the induction hypothesis foru β uβ
, we know that for anyvβ² β¦ wβ² β u
,vβ² β¦ wβ²
factorsuβ
. Now we apply the lemma sub-inv-trans, which gives us someuβ
such that(dom uβ²) β¦ (cod uβ²)
factorsuβ
intouβ
. We show thatv β¦ w
also factorsuβ
intouβ
. Fromdom uβ β dom uβ²
anddom uβ² β v
, we havedom uβ β v
. Fromw β cod uβ²
andcod uβ² β cod uβ
, we havew β cod uβ
, and this case is complete.Case
β-fun
.uββ β uββ uββ β uββ --------------------- uββ β¦ uββ β uββ β¦ uββ
Given that
v β¦ w β uββ β¦ uββ
, we havev β‘ uββ
andw β‘ uββ
. We show thatuββ β¦ uββ
factorsuββ β¦ uββ
into itself. We need to show thatdom (uββ β¦ uββ) β uββ
anduββ β cod (uββ β¦ uββ)
, but that is equivalent to our premisesuββ β uββ
anduββ β uββ
.Case
β-dist
.--------------------------------------------- uββ β¦ (uββ β uββ) β (uββ β¦ uββ) β (uββ β¦ uββ)
Given that
v β¦ w β uββ β¦ (uββ β uββ)
, we havev β‘ uββ
andw β‘ uββ β uββ
. We show thatuββ β¦ (uββ β uββ)
factors(uββ β¦ uββ) β (uββ β¦ uββ)
into itself. We haveuββ β uββ β uββ
, and alsouββ β uββ β uββ β uββ
, so the proof is complete.
We conclude this section with two corollaries of the sub-inv lemma. First, we have the following property that is convenient to use in later proofs. We specialize the premise to just v β¦ w β uβ
and we modify the conclusion to say that for every vβ² β¦ wβ² β uβ
, we have vβ² β v
.
sub-inv-fun : β{v w uβ : Value} β (v β¦ w) β uβ ----------------------------------------------------- β Ξ£[ uβ β Value ] all-funs uβ Γ uβ β uβ Γ (β{vβ² wβ²} β (vβ² β¦ wβ²) β uβ β vβ² β v) Γ w β cod uβ sub-inv-fun{v}{w}{uβ} abc with sub-inv abc {v}{w} refl ... | β¨ uβ , β¨ f , β¨ uββuβ , β¨ db , cc β© β© β© β© = β¨ uβ , β¨ f , β¨ uββuβ , β¨ G , cc β© β© β© β© where G : β{D E} β (D β¦ E) β uβ β D β v G{D}{E} m = β-trans (βββ (β¦βββdom f m)) db
The second corollary is the inversion rule that one would expect for less-than with functions on the left and right-hand sides.
β¦ββ¦-inv : β{v w vβ² wβ²} β v β¦ w β vβ² β¦ wβ² ----------------- β vβ² β v Γ w β wβ² β¦ββ¦-inv{v}{w}{vβ²}{wβ²} lt with sub-inv-fun lt ... | β¨ Ξ , β¨ f , β¨ Ξβv34 , β¨ lt1 , lt2 β© β© β© β© with all-funsβ f ... | β¨ u , β¨ uβ² , uβ¦uβ²βΞ β© β© with Ξβv34 uβ¦uβ²βΞ ... | refl = let codΞβwβ² = ββ¦βcodβ Ξβv34 in β¨ lt1 uβ¦uβ²βΞ , β-trans lt2 (βββ codΞβwβ²) β©
Notes
The denotational semantics presented in this chapter is an example of a filter model (Barendregt, Coppo, Dezani-Ciancaglini, 1983). Filter models use type systems with intersection types to precisely characterize runtime behavior (Coppo, Dezani-Ciancaglini, and Salle, 1979). The notation that we use in this chapter is not that of type systems and intersection types, but the Value
data type is isomorphic to types (β¦
is β
, β
is β§
, β₯
is β€
), the β
relation is the inverse of subtyping <:
, and the evaluation relation Ο β’ M β v
is isomorphic to a type system. Write Ξ
instead of Ο
, A
instead of v
, and replace β
with :
and one has a typing judgement Ξ β’ M : A
. By varying the definition of subtyping and using different choices of type atoms, intersection type systems provide semantics for many different untyped Ξ» calculi, from full beta to the lazy and call-by-value calculi (Alessi, Barbanera, and Dezani-Ciancaglini, 2006) (Rocca and Paolini, 2004). The denotational semantics in this chapter corresponds to the BCD system (Barendregt, Coppo, Dezani-Ciancaglini, 1983). Part 3 of the book Lambda Calculus with Types describes a framework for intersection type systems that enables results similar to the ones in this chapter, but for the entire family of intersection type systems (Barendregt, Dekkers, and Statman, 2013).
The two ideas of using finite tables to represent functions and of relaxing table lookup to enable self application first appeared in a technical report by Gordon Plotkin (1972) and are later described in an article in Theoretical Computer Science (Plotkin 1993). In that work, the inductive definition of Value
is a bit different than the one we use:
Value = C + βf(Value) Γ βf(Value)
where C
is a set of constants and βf
means finite powerset. The pairs in βf(Value) Γ βf(Value)
represent input-output mappings, just as in this chapter. The finite powersets are used to enable a function table to appear in the input and in the output. These differences amount to changing where the recursion appears in the definition of Value
. Plotkinβs model is an example of a graph model of the untyped lambda calculus (Barendregt, 1984). In a graph model, the semantics is presented as a function from programs and environments to (possibly infinite) sets of values. The semantics in this chapter is instead defined as a relation, but set-valued functions are isomorphic to relations. Indeed, we present the semantics as a function in the next chapter and prove that it is equivalent to the relational version.
Dana Scottβs β(Ο) (1976) and Engelerβs B(A) (1981) are two more examples of graph models. Both use the following inductive definition of Value
.
Value = C + βf(Value) Γ Value
The use of Value
instead of βf(Value)
in the output does not restrict expressiveness compared to Plotkinβs model because the semantics use sets of values and a pair of sets (V, Vβ²)
can be represented as a set of pairs { (V, vβ²) | vβ² β Vβ² }
. In Scottβs β(Ο), the above values are mapped to and from the natural numbers using a kind of Godel encoding.
References
Intersection Types and Lambda Models. Fabio Alessi, Franco Barbanera, and Mariangiola Dezani-Ciancaglini, Theoretical Compututer Science, vol. 355, pages 108-126, 2006.
The Lambda Calculus. H.P. Barendregt, 1984.
A filter lambda model and the completeness of type assignment. Henk Barendregt, Mario Coppo, and Mariangiola Dezani-Ciancaglini, Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 48, pages 931-940, 1983.
Lambda Calculus with Types. Henk Barendregt, Wil Dekkers, and Richard Statman, Cambridge University Press, Perspectives in Logic, 2013.
Functional characterization of some semantic equalities inside Ξ»-calculus. Mario Coppo, Mariangiola Dezani-Ciancaglini, and Patrick Salle, in Sixth Colloquium on Automata, Languages and Programming. Springer, pages 133β146, 1979.
Algebras and combinators. Erwin Engeler, Algebra Universalis, vol. 13, pages 389-392, 1981.
A Set-Theoretical Definition of Application. Gordon D. Plotkin, University of Edinburgh, Technical Report MIP-R-95, 1972.
Set-theoretical and other elementary models of the Ξ»-calculus. Gordon D. Plotkin, Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 121, pages 351-409, 1993.
The Parametric Lambda Calculus. Simona Ronchi Della Rocca and Luca Paolini, Springer, 2004.
Data Types as Lattices. Dana Scott, SIAM Journal on Computing, vol. 5, pages 522-587, 1976.
Unicode
This chapter uses the following unicode:
β₯ U+22A5 UP TACK (\bot)
β¦ U+21A6 RIGHTWARDS ARROW FROM BAR (\mapsto)
β U+2294 SQUARE CUP (\lub)
β U+2291 SQUARE IMAGE OF OR EQUAL TO (\sqsubseteq)
β’ U+22A2 RIGHT TACK (\|- or \vdash)
β U+2193 DOWNWARDS ARROW (\d)
αΆ U+1D9C MODIFIER LETTER SMALL C (\^c)
β° U+2130 SCRIPT CAPITAL E (\McE)
β U+2243 ASYMPTOTICALLY EQUAL TO (\~- or \simeq)
β U+2208 ELEMENT OF (\in)
β U+2286 SUBSET OF OR EQUAL TO (\sub= or \subseteq)